NihilismAbsurdism.Blogspot.com

"The Absurd" refers to the conflict between the human tendency to seek inherent meaning in life and the human inability to find any.

Nihilism : from the Latin nihil, nothing) is the philosophical doctrine suggesting the negation of one or more putatively meaningful aspects of life

Wednesday, November 17, 2010

Nietzsche





To begin to understand Nihilism one has to separate at least the two main distinctions between what Nihilism means. One connotes Negativity and the other Emptiness although distinct from Nietzsche nevertheless bear it some partial resemblance. The Nihilists of Emptiness essentially that of the BUDDHISTS or Hindus both of which hold that the world we live in and seem to know has no ultimate reality and that our attachment to it is an a attachment to an allusion. Reality itself has neither name nor form and what has name and form is but a painful dreaming and all reasonable men would escape if they knew how and that the attachment was to nothingness.

Life is without sense and point there is a ceaseless alternation of birth and death and birth again the constant turning the wheel of existence going nowhere eternally if it is salvation we want it is from life that me must seek. The Oriental pessimism articulated in Europe by the philosophy of Arthur Schopenhauer is based on a set of metaphorical views closely akin to those of Nietzsche. However as we shall see he did not draw the same consequences which Schopenhauer and the orientals did and it was the word 'pessimism' that opened his eyes to the opposite ideal.

Part of what we must clarify is the manner in which Nietzsche was able on the basis of a
metaphysical Nihilism of the most uncompromising sort to justify an attitude toward life which in its affirmative was in every respect discordant with the Nihilism of EMPTINESS, his new way was yes. To emphasize how Nietzsche's version of Nihilism differed from the norm he had in mind a thoroughly disillusioned conception of a world which is as hostile to human aspiration as he could imagine it to be. It is hostile not because it or anything other than us has goals of its own but because it is utterly indifferent to what we either believe or hope. Once man attains a realization that the alleged real or true world is of human provenance, created in response to certain unfulfilled human needs, a fabrication which is philosophically unjustified and psychologically comprehensible, then he achieves the final form of Nihilism: a disbelief in any world alternative and metaphysically preferable to this one. At the same time he regards this world as the only one, however unstructured and purposeless it may be, and however valueless.


Fredrich Nietzsche



Frederich Nietzsche



God is dead!

When Nietzsche declared “God is dead” he meant that Judeo- Christianity had been lost as a guiding force in their lives and there is nothing to replace it. People are creative they will find something, sex, science, education, an alternative ethical system, something. Science may have pushed God off to the sidelines and taken over the reigns, maybe, yet I believe there is still a very strong religious contingent still at work out there. I’ll explain later why I don’t think that this is a valid comparison, religion vs nihilism. People still have faith, as misplaced as it is it is theirs. This faith does not necessarily need to be placed on religions doorstep. We can put that faith to work in real places.

With approximately 6.8 billion people on the planet approximately 6 billion are of some religious faith. That is about 90% of the planet! It’s not the faith that bothers me it is the religiosity. We are still arguing Wade vs Roe and Creationism vs Evolution and this is 2011 not 1850. If it takes 150 years for 10-14% of the population to choose to leave God out of the game I’d bet the other 86-94% are a little reticent about exchanging their faith for science or sex or nihilism or even the ‘Yes’ version of nihilism Nietzsche professed. I will explain his Copernican revolution further on. There are a few versions of nihilism all negative and pessimistic. Nietzsche turns the no of nihilism into a life affirming ‘yes’.

World Religions

Four largest religions↓

Adherents↓

% of World Population↓

Wikipage↓

World Population

6.8 billion

Figure used by individual articles

Christianity

1.9 billion - 2.1 billion

29% - 32%

Christianity by country

Islam

1.3 billion - 1.57 billion

19% - 21%

Islam by country

Hinduism

800 million - 900 million

14% - 20%

Hinduism by country

Buddhism

500 million - 1 billion

7% - 19%

Buddhism by country

Total

4.65 billion - 6.17 billion

68.38% - 90.73%



Religion

Adherents

Christianity

2.1 billion

Islam

1.5 billion

Irreligious/agnostic/atheism

1.1 billion

Hinduism

900 million

Chinese traditional religion

394 million

Buddhism

376 million

Animist religions

300 million

African traditional/diasporic religions

100 million

Sikhism

23 million

Juche

19 million

Spiritism

15 million

Judaism

14 million

Baha'i

7 million

Jainism

4.2 million

Shinto

4 million

Cao Dai

4 million

Zoroastrianism

2.6 million

Tenrikyo

2 million

Neo-Paganism

1 million

Unitarian Universalism

800,000

Rastafari Movement

600,000

What is the meaning of Nihilism in America today?

Can a movie like Pulp Fiction really convince anyone that Nihilism is a good thing and it’s going to take the place of people’s faith? The problem with these types of genre films is that they subversively get us to turn our heads away from real bullet and they cause more harm than good. Like the Rocky Horror Picture show it will be trotted out each year as the cult movie de-jure although The Rocky Horror Picture show had its redeeming qualities. It was funny. Tarantino’s flick would scare even Richard Dawkins back to Jesus but Dawkins knows there are livable real time solutions to dogma, mysticism, existentialism, materialism and all the other schisms religion has perpetrated on the world for hundreds and hundreds of years. The question is can a small population of nihilists exist without an objective source for its ethics and morals without disturbing the mainstream?

Traditional Nihilist ‘movements’ have incorporated violence as their modus operendi, a means to advance their objectives getting noticed, the new avaunt guard. Turgenev’s ‘Fathers and Sons’ was a portrait of a Russian Nihilist Movement in the 19th century(1850-1860) which was just a movement of disgruntled kids demonstrating their dissatisfaction with everything their parents and authority stood for. There were numerous factions within the movement where their divisiveness was mainly due to the choice of whether to use violence or not and that was the movement, 150 years ago, in a remote location in Russia. They probably had good reason to be angry. The younger crowd was all for using violence but the older members understandably vowed against it.

I’m sure Tarantino researched that aspect carefully because Pulp Fiction was lawless, sociopathic and pandered to the young urban sub culture (the disenfranchised, the marginalized the hopeless) with endless mindless gratuitous violence. Because we no longer believe in God doesn’t mean we don’t need police or courts or laws, or a personal ethical standard, all absent in the film. It is curious why Tarantino chose this particular brand of Nihilism, well not really. That genre generates tremendous revenue in LA, hence Bruce Willis and John Travolta. The only missing character was Al Pacino blazing away with a bazooka blowing up kindergarten kids in schoolyards.

If you consider Camus and Nietzsche nihilists neither of them advocated a violent type of Nihilism although they would disagree fundamentally on most other concepts. In fact Nietzsche’s brand was a ‘yes’ type of Nihilism not a ‘no’ type. His was a Copernican revolution. No guns. It begs the question. Would we have any more violence than we’ve already had? It seems that God is not quite dead yet though with 68%-91% of the worlds population still practices some kind of religion and a mere 14% not practicing. This does not suggest that they are Nihilists. That is 1 billion people or 1/7 of the world’s population. Hardly a revolution! When we talk about Nihilism it is usually philosophically, metaphysically not ideologically as is the case in the movie. Most people do not read about or understand Nihilism (s). It is a difficult topic, far to complex for the average person. It drove Nietzsche mad.

There is evidence of such movements in the US and Europe. Hot button issues end up on the big screen as a cult classic like Pulp Fiction. Or the sub culture names songs or bands around the idea as in The Nihilist Spasm Band or the group who wrote the Monday Night Football Theme ‘Absurd’. They generate huge revenues and in the process mislead audiences as to the real meaning of issues like Nihilism, manufacturing false ideas and leaving incorrect impressions about a very serious subject. It is understandable why these movements originate at universities and filter down to the sub culture because it is the students of philosophy, politics, film and psychology that pass the information down the chain. I would consider John Travolta and Quentin Tarantino students, students of film and sub culture behavior. Their presence in a film like that is a good indicator as to who the target audience is going to be.

(Simplified) Relationship between existentialism, absurdism and nihilism



Atheistic existentialism

Theistic existentialism

Absurdism

Nihilism

1. There is such a thing as meaningvalue or

Yes

Yes

Yes

No

2. There is inherent meaning in the universe (either intrinsic or from God)

No

Maybe, but humans must have faith to believe there is

Maybe, but humans can never know it

No

3. Individuals can create meaning in life themselves

Yes, it is essential that they do

Yes, but that meaning must incorporate God

Yes, but it is not essential

No, because there is no such meaning to create

4. The pursuit of intrinsic or extrinsic meaning in the universe is possible

No, and the pursuit itself is meaningless

Yes, and the pursuit itself may have meaning

No, but the pursuit itself may have meaning

No, and the pursuit itself is meaningless

5. The pursuit of constructed meaning is possible

Yes, thus the goal of existentialism

Yes, thus the goal of existentialism

Maybe

No

6. There is a solution to the individual's desire to seek meaning

Yes, the creation of one's own meaning

Yes, the creation of one's own meaning before God

Yes, to some extent (or possibly completely) through acknowledging though continuing to revolt against the Absurd

No

I’ve been contrasting Nihilism with religion as an objective framework or foundation of values and meaning, but there are other objective systems of ethics however. We might compare Nihilism to Aristotelian ethics as an example. I won’t talk about Aristotle suffice it say he says that things have natures or essences and that what is best for a thing is to achieve or realize its essence. A bit metaphysical for me but it could be an objective yard stick to stave off nihilism. This suggests things have capacities and capabilities like humans who have a set that no other creature or thing has that we are aware of and that is reason. This is our essential ability. Here is where Nietzsche’s Copernican turn comes into play. He turns the ‘NO’ in Nihilism into an affirming ‘yes’ even though his brand of Nihilism is more negative than the Oriental Schopenhauer version.

Introduction to Nietzschean Nihilism

It is sometimes thought or hoped that in addition to the commonly acknowledged modes of achieving positive knowledge of the world –through sense experience and scientific investigation – art provides us with a special way of attaining to perhaps a special class of truths; and these are said to have as great a claim to objectivity as any other. ART together with its escapes and pleasures has been thought to yield intellectual benefits as well of possibly a very high order conducting us to factual insights perhaps not otherwise accessible to mere human cognition.

The radical nature of Nietzsche’s thought even in its first significant expression may be seen in the fact that he is indeed prepared to allow that art has no less a claim than sense or science to objective truth. But this is because neither sense nor science can make any stronger claim to truth than art.

There is an analogy to be found between art and cognition (so called) regarding both their origin and their function: each consists in illusions, the illusions of science and sense making life possible, and the illusions of art making it bearable.

Nietzsche’s reasons for these highly skeptical conclusions consist in certain epistemological (theory of knowledge) analysis rather like those often urged later by Bertrand Russell according to which our perceptions are said not to resemble their causes so that the language we employ learned in connection with the having of perceptions does not describe the world as it really is. Language rather describes- insofar as in Nietzsche’s view we may think of language as descriptive at all-the illusions we take for reality. At this point Nietzsche was supposing that there might be an order or structure in the world which we were capable of capturing. Yet given his ideas concerning the origin and function of our language, we could not say what the world might be in fact like even if , per impossible , we were in the position to experience whatever causes our perceptions. We plainly could not apply our terms to these causes.

Our primitive mode of contact with the world is essentially as artists, as more or less unwitting makers of images and metaphors transforming rather than reproducing our experiences, themselves transformations and not duplications of their causes and objects. But 'metaphors' through time and use become resolved into concepts and concepts elaborated into systems and ultimately these "edifices of concepts exhibit the rigid regularity of a Roman columbarium." One must vastly admire the architectural genius of mankind which builds "an infinitely complex cathedral of concepts upon shifting foundations and flowing waters, so to speak." But this admiration must be restricted to the structuring genius of the collective human intellect not to its capacity for discovering truth in any conventional sense of the term because at bottom our concepts are the residue of metaphors and the architecture of our conceptual structure is "anthropomorphic through and through and contains not a single point of which is 'true-in-itself,' objective and universal apart from man."

We dwell in a structure we have built for ourselves and could not for a moment survive as recognizably ourselves "outside the prison walls of these beliefs."



Part 1

Nihilism connotes Negativity and Emptiness; in fact it denotes two bodies of thought that although distinct from Nietzsche’s never the less bear it some partial resemblance. The Nihilism of Emptiness is essentially that of Buddhist or Hindu teaching both of which hold that the world w e live in and seem to know has no ultimate reality and that our attachment to it is an attachment to illusion. Reality itself has neither name nor form and what has name and form is but a painful dreaming from which all reasonable men would wish to escape if they knew the way and knew that their attachment was to nothingness. Life is without sense and point there is a ceaseless alternation of birth and death and birth again the constantly turning wheel of existence going nowhere eternally; if we wish salvation it is salvation from life that we must seek. This Oriental pessimism articulated in Europe in the philosophy of Arthur Schopenhauer is based upon a set of metaphysical views which are closely akin to those that Nietzsche advanced as his own. He sought, he tells us, "to get to the bottom of the question of [European] pessimism and liberate it from the half-Christian, half-German narrowness and stupidity in which it has finally presented itself to our century."3 He did not however draw the same consequences which Schopenhauer and the Oriental philosophers did and Nietzsche adds that whoever had analyzed pessimism " has perhaps just thereby without really desiring it opened his eyes to behold the opposite ideal : the ideal of the most world-approving exuberant and vivacious man."4 This was his Copernican revolution.

Part of what we must clarify then is the manner in which Nietzsche was able on the basis of a metaphysical Nihilism of the most uncompromising sort to justify an attitude toward life which in its affirmative was in every respect discordant with the Nihilism of Emptiness: his “new way to ‘YES’”.5

Part 2

The Nihilism of Negativity as I shall call it is exemplified in the movement properly known as 'NIHILISM', which flourished in the latter decades of the 19th c in Europe especially in the 1850's -1860's in Russia and which found it most respectable expression in Turgenev's 'Fathers and Sons' (1861). Russian Nihilism was essentially a negative and destructive attitude against a body of moral, political and religious teachings found or felt by the Nihilists to be confining and obscurantist.

As against their elders, Nihilists claimed that they believed in nothing, though what this specifically meant was that they held in total discredit the beliefs, tastes, and attitudes of their elders and those in current authority as in most revolutions. "Nihilism in the St. Petersburg style- i.e., belief in unbelief to the point of martyrdom for it, shows always and above all the need for belief...."6 In actual fact they believed, in an uncritical and wholesale manner, in a crudely materialistic interpretation of science. Materialism, the word is often used to stand for the view that everything is material and that there is nothing mental at all: "All matter, no mind." What exactly does this mean? This materialistic interpretation of science will be discussed later.

It is the typical 'mind-body' problem that faced Descartes. His solution was the cogito: cogito ergo sum - "I think therefore I am". It was basically in the name of science that they proclaimed, as invalid, the principles they inveighed (violently attacked) against. But inasmuch as their understanding of science was filtered through a version of materialism which they mistook for science itself or which if more sophisticated they took to be the only attitude compatible with and justified by science there was an undeniable component of belief indeed faith which interpenetrated their nihilism and rendered it halfhearted. Nihilists believed that there was no such thing as meaning or value, no inherent value in the universe, pursuit of meaning was not possible, the pursuit of constructed meaning was not possible, there is no solution to the individuals desire to seek meaning and there should be no room here for the kind of faith or belief posed here!

Part 3

The Enlightenment Ideal

The 19th c, in its way was as much an age of faith as was the 12th c. Almost any European thinker of this epoch appears to us today as a kind of visionary committed to one or another program of salvation and to one or other simple way of achieving it. It was as though the needs and hopes which had found satisfaction in religion still perdurable (permanently durable) in an era when religion itself no longer could be credited and something else - science, education, revolution, evolution, socialism, business enterprise or, latterly, sex -must be seized upon to fill the place left empty and to discharge the office vacated by religious beliefs which could not now sustain.

And so it was with Nihilism. It was not so much a matter of science driving out faith as of one faith replacing another. The hope for a better dispensation in another life was replaced by a psychologically indistinguishable hope for a better dispensation in this one for a sound and scientifically based set of institutions which would come about almost inevitably once the old orders and the vested interests were swept away together with the ideas which protected and supported them.

This was recognizably the ideal of the Enlightenment but expressed a century later with a certain drama and violence in part perhaps because it now had become the ideology of the youthful and disenfranchised sons in rebellion against their fathers.



In Fathers and sons Barazov repudiates everything that cannot be explained by the laws of natural science, striving for reality rather than negation and he embodies the spirit of revolution. This gives you a clue as to the true nature of this touchingly adolescent attitude that relied on science and faith through revolution to form a new society. This type of Russian Nihilism took place locally about 1850 to 1860

Nietzsche's more Negative Nihilism. The Copernican Twist.

Nietzsche was not less but more negativistic than his Nihilistic contemporaries (though he was not part of that movement in any sense whatsoever) and he is celebrated, attacked or applauded for his bitter denunciations of many of the same traditions, beliefs and institutions which they explicitly repudiated.

His Nihilism nevertheless is not an ideology (the body of ideas characteristic of a particular individual, group or culture) but a metaphysic (the underlying nature of things) and in no respect is his difference from Nihilists more marked than in his attitude towards science.

“Science he regards not as a repository of truths or a method for discovering them but as a set of convenient fictions of useful conventions, which has as much and as little basis in reality as any alleged set of fictions which might be thought to conflict with it. Science, no more and no less than religion, morality and art was an instance of what he termed Will-To-Power, an impulse and a drive to impose upon an essentially chaotic reality a form and structure to shape it into a world congenial to human understanding while habitable by human intelligence. But this was its sole justification and any imposed form which worked to the same purpose would be equally justifiable, content counting for less than function –counting, indeed for nothing at all”.

Science in a sense of truth is not true. But in the sense in which it is not true, neither is anything else; and relative to this theory of truth which was his, Nietzsche must say that he did not, because in metaphysical honesty he could not believe in anything. His was accordingly a deep and total Nihilism, from the vantage point of which the contest of the Russian Nihilists with their declared ideological enemies was but an instance in the struggle of wills, a struggle for power and form which, as Nietzsche saw it, characterizes human life everywhere and always and, in a sense was the single characteristic he was prepared to ascribe to the universe at large, which he saw as an eternal strife of will with will.

Both of the non-Nietzschean forms of Nihilism derive from much the same attitude. Each believes that there ought to be some order or external purpose in the world. The Nihilism of Emptiness, Schopenhauer’s Nihilism presupposes an outlook, become habitual, in accordance with which purposes are established from without. This Nihilism expresses a disappointment that there is no such purpose when in fact the state of mind that demands that there be one ought to be overcome. With its overcoming, the grounds for pessimism and despair are disqualified. Russian Nihilism, meanwhile is typical of thought that derives from the same habit just mentioned that there is an external authority to whom or to which we must appeal in order to determine the purpose of life: “having learnt not to believe in one authority, [it] sought to find another” – in this case Science. But men find it difficult to function in this world without supposing one or another external source of authority and significance, “if not God or Science, then Conscience, Reason, Social Instinct or History”, conceived of as “an immanent spirit with built-in purpose to which one may surrender”. It is a general tendency of the human mind which to Nietzsche is ultimately a disastrous disposition to imagine and to seek to identify a purposive armature a basis for significance in the world itself something objective to which men may submit and in which they may find a meaning for themselves. The Nihilism of Emptiness as a mood of thought and as a psychological condition arises in direct consequence of the realization or suspicion that really there is no such thing to be found no world order in which we ourselves are integral parts and such that our entire value derives from being related to it in determined ways. Perhaps we then like the Buddhists write off the entire thing as a dream and seek no longer to be bothered by what has no substance. Or, like so many philosophers and visionaries we invent in compensation, “a world which lies beyond this one a true world “, in contrast with which this world is completely disvalued. But once a man attains a realization that the alleged real or true world is of human provenance created in response to certain unfulfilled human needs, a fabrication which is philosophically unjustified if psychologically comprehensible then he achieves the final form of Nihilism: a disbelief in any world alternative and metaphysically preferable to this one. At the same time he regards this world as the only one however unstructured and purposeless it may be and however valueless.

The claim that the world is valueless is not to say that it has some low value in the scheme of values as when we say of something that it is of little worth or none but rather it is not the kind of thing of which it logically makes sense to say either that it is worth little or that it has such and such a higher value. Values have no more application to the world than weights do to numbers : to say that the number two is weightless is not to say that it is very light but that it is senseless to assign it any weight at all. This would be Nietzsche’s view. Strictly it follows that the world has no value from the fact that there is nothing in it which might sensibly be supposed to have value. There is neither order nor purpose, things nor facts, nothing there whatever to which our beliefs can correspond. So that all our beliefs are false. This he regards as “the extremist form of nihilism –the insight that every belief every taking for true is necessarily false: because there is no true world at all”. This is a highly dramatized rejection of the Correspondence Theory of Truth.

Nietzsche’s claims in behalf of this extreme Nihilism are in need of clarification before we raise question as to whether there is compelling reason for endorsing them. His Nihilism has little to do with ordinary political connotations of the term and that by “Nihilism” he had in mind a thoroughly disillusioned conception of the world which is hostile to human aspirations as he could imagine it to be. It is hostile not because it or anything other than us has goals of its own but because it is utterly indifferent to what we either believe or hope. This negative fact should not lead us to a “negation, a no, a will to nothingness.” Rather he felt it is an intoxicating fact to know that the world is devoid of form and meaning, encouraging if anything “ a Dionysian yes to the world as it is without exceptions, exemptions or deductions.” To affirm such a view he thought required considerable courage for it meant that we must abandon hopes and expectations which had comforted men through religions and philosophies from the beginning. He felt we should adopt his formula of Amor Fati – loving one’s fate, accepting without palliative or protection the results of a most thoroughgoing critique of philosophical and scientific ideas seen as fiction the products of some human need for security and then endeavoring to live in a world impervious to these needs, to say YES to the cosmic insignificance not only of oneself and of human beings generally but also of life and nature as a whole. So the fate which he encourages to accept and indeed to love is made considerably more difficult through this purposeless repetitiveness of the universe – eternal recurrence –that is the extreme form of Nihilism : nothingness (“meaninglessness”) forever



Hegel's Correspondence of Truth

Hegel tried to distance his philosophy from psychology by presenting truth as being an external self–moving object instead of being related to inner, subjective thoughts. Hegel's truth is analogous to the mechanics of a material body in motion under the influence of its own inner force. "Truth is its own self–movement within itself."[56] Teleological truth moves itself in the three–step form of dialectical triplicity toward the final goal of perfect, final, absolute truth. For Hegel, the progression of philosophical truth is a resolution of past oppositions into increasingly more accurate approximations to absolute truth. Chalybäusthesis", "antithesis", and "synthesis" to describe Hegel's dialectical triplicity. The "thesis" consists of an incomplete historical movement. To resolve the incompletion, an "antithesis" occurs which opposes the "thesis." In turn, the "synthesis" appears when the "thesis" and "antithesis" become reconciled and a higher level of truth is obtained. This "synthesis" thereby becomes a "thesis," which will again necessitate an "antithesis," requiring a new "synthesis" until a final state is reached as the result of reason's historical movement. History is the Absolute Spirit moving toward a goal. This historical progression will finally conclude itself when the Absolute Spirit understands its own infinite self at the very end of history. Absolute Spirit will then be the complete expression of an infinite God. used the terms "



Friedrich Wilhelm Nietzsche
Full name Friedrich Wilhelm Nietzsche
Born October 15, 1844
Died August 25, 1900(1900-08-25) (aged 55)

Weimar, Saxony, German Empire
Era 19th century philosophy
Region Western Philosophy
School Weimar Classicism; precursor to Continental philosophy, existentialism, Individualism, postmodernism, poststructuralism
Main interests aesthetics, ethics, ontology, philosophy of history, psychology, value-theory, poetry
Notable ideas Apollonian and Dionysian, death of God, eternal recurrence, herd-instinct, master-slave morality, Übermensch, perspectivism, will to power, ressentiment, der letzte Mensch
Signature

Friedrich Wilhelm Nietzsche (German pronunciation: [ˈfʁiːdʁɪç ˈvɪlhɛlm ˈniːtsʃə]; in English UK: /ˈniːtʃə/, US: /ˈniːtʃi/[1]) (October 15, 1844 – August 25, 1900) was a 19th-century German philosopher and classical philologist. He wrote critical texts on religion, morality, contemporary culture, philosophy and science, displaying a fondness for metaphor, irony and aphorism.

Nietzsche's influence remains substantial within and beyond philosophy, notably in existentialism and postmodernism. His style and radical questioning of the value and objectivity of truth have resulted in much commentary and interpretation, mostly in the continental tradition. His key ideas include the death of God, perspectivism, the Übermensch, the eternal recurrence, and the will to power. Central to his philosophy is the idea of “life-affirmation,” which involves an honest questioning of all doctrines that drain life's expansive energies, however socially prevalent those views might be.[2]

Nietzsche began his career as a classical philologist before turning to philosophy. At the age of 24 he was appointed to the Chair of Classical Philology at the University of Basel (the youngest individual to have held this position), but resigned in 1879 due to health problems that plagued him most of his life. In 1889 he became mentally ill, possibly due to atypical general paralysis attributed to tertiary syphilis.[3] He lived his remaining years in the care of his mother until her death in 1897, then under the care of his sister until his death in 1900.

Life

Youth (1844–1869)

Born on October 15, 1844, Nietzsche grew up in the small town of Röcken, near Leipzig, in the Prussian Province of Saxony. He was named after King Frederick William IV of Prussia, who turned 49 on the day of Nietzsche's birth. (Nietzsche later dropped his given middle name, "Wilhelm".)[4] Nietzsche's parents, Carl Ludwig Nietzsche (1813–1849), a Lutheran pastor and former teacher, and Franziska Oehler (1826–1897), married in 1843, the year before their son's birth, and had two other children: a daughter, Elisabeth Förster-Nietzsche, born in 1846, and a second son, Ludwig Joseph, born in 1848. Nietzsche's father died from a brain ailment in 1849; his younger brother died in 1850. The family then moved to Naumburg, where they lived with Nietzsche's paternal grandmother and his father's two unmarried sisters. After the death of Nietzsche's grandmother in 1856, the family moved into their own house.



Nietzsche, 1861

Nietzsche attended a boys' school and then later a private school, where he became friends with Gustav Krug and Wilhelm Pinder, both of whom came from very respected families. In 1854, he began to attend Pforta in Naumburg, but after he showed particular talents in music and language, the internationally recognised Schulpforta admitted him as a pupil, and there he continued his studies from 1858 to 1864. Here he became friends with Paul Deussen and Carl von Gersdorff. He also found time to work on poems and musical compositions. At Schulpforta, Nietzsche received an important introduction to literature, particularly that of the ancient Greeks and Romans, and for the first time experienced a distance from his family life in a small-town Christian environment.



Nietzsche, 1864

After graduation in 1864 Nietzsche commenced studies in theology and classical philology at the University of Bonn. For a short time he and Deussen became members of the Burschenschaft Frankonia. After one semester (and to the anger of his mother) he stopped his theological studies and lost his faith.[5] This may have happened in part because of his reading around this time of David Strauss's Life of Jesus, which had a profound effect on the young Nietzsche,[5] though in an essay entitled Fate and History written in 1862, Nietzsche had already argued that historical research had discredited the central teachings of Christianity.[6] Nietzsche then concentrated on studying philology under Professor Friedrich Wilhelm Ritschl, whom he followed to the University of Leipzig the next year. There he became close friends with fellow-student Erwin Rohde. Nietzsche's first philological publications appeared soon after.

In 1865 Nietzsche thoroughly studied the works of Arthur Schopenhauer. He owed the awakening of his philosophical interest to reading his Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung and later admitted that he was one of the few thinkers that he respected, dedicating to him his essay Schopenhauer als Erzieher (Schopenhauer as Educator), one of his Untimely Meditations.

In 1866 he read Friedrich Albert Lange's History of Materialism. Schopenhauer and Lange influenced him. Schopenhauer was especially significant in the development of Nietzsche's later thought. Lange's descriptions of Kant's anti-materialistic philosophy, the rise of European Materialism, Europe's increased concern with science, Darwin's theory, and the general rebellion against tradition and authority greatly intrigued Nietzsche. The cultural environment encouraged him to expand his horizons beyond philology and to continue his study of philosophy.

In 1867 Nietzsche signed up for one year of voluntary service with the Prussian artillery division in Naumburg. However, a riding accident in March 1868 left him unfit for service.[7] Consequently Nietzsche turned his attention to his studies again, completing them and first meeting with Richard Wagner later that year.



Mid-October 1871. From left: Erwin Rohde, Carl von Gersdorff, Nietzsche

In part because of Ritschl's support, Nietzsche received a remarkable offer to become professor of classical philology at the University of Basel. He was only 24 years old and had neither completed his doctorate nor received his teaching certificate. Despite the fact that the offer came at a time when he was considering giving up philology for science, he accepted.[9] To this day, Nietzsche is still among the youngest of the tenured Classics professors on record.[10] Before moving to Basel, Nietzsche renounced his Prussian citizenship: for the rest of his life he remained officially stateless.[11]

Nevertheless, Nietzsche served in the Prussian forces during the Franco-Prussian War of 1870 to 1871 as a medical orderly. In his short time in the military he experienced much, and witnessed the traumatic effects of battle. He also contracted diphtheria and dysentery. Walter Kaufmann speculates that he might also have contracted syphilis along with his other infections at this time, and some biographers speculate that syphilis caused his eventual madness, though there is some disagreement on this matter.[12][13] On returning to Basel in 1870 Nietzsche observed the establishment of the German Empire and the following era of Otto von Bismarck as an outsider and with a degree of skepticism regarding its genuineness. At the University, he delivered his inaugural lecture, "Homer and Classical Philology". Nietzsche also met Franz Overbeck, a professor of theology, who remained his friend throughout his life. Afrikan Spir,[14] a little-known Russian philosopher and author of Denken und Wirklichkeit (1873), and his colleague the historian Jacob Burckhardt, whose lectures Nietzsche frequently attended, began to exercise significant influence on Nietzsche during this time.

Nietzsche had already met Richard Wagner in Leipzig in 1868, and (some time later) Wagner's wife Cosima. Nietzsche admired both greatly, and during his time at Basel frequently visited Wagner's house in Tribschen in the Canton of Lucerne. The Wagners brought Nietzsche into their most intimate circle, and enjoyed the attention he gave to the beginning of the Bayreuth Festival Theatre. In 1870 he gave Cosima Wagner the manuscript of 'The Genesis of the Tragic Idea' as a birthday gift. In 1872 Nietzsche published his first book, The Birth of Tragedy. However, his colleagues in the field of classical philology, including Ritschl, expressed little enthusiasm for the work, in which Nietzsche eschewed the classical philologic method in favor of a more speculative approach. In a polemic, Philology of the Future, Ulrich von Wilamowitz-Moellendorff dampened the book's reception and increased its notoriety. In response, Rohde (by now a professor in Kiel) and Wagner came to Nietzsche's defense. Nietzsche remarked freely about the isolation he felt within the philological community and attempted to attain a position in philosophy at Basel, though unsuccessfully.



Nietzsche in Basel, ca. 1875

Between 1873 and 1876, Nietzsche published separately four long essays: David Strauss: the Confessor and the Writer, On the Use and Abuse of History for Life, Schopenhauer as Educator, and Richard Wagner in Bayreuth. (These four later appeared in a collected edition under the title, Untimely Meditations.) The four essays shared the orientation of a cultural critique, challenging the developing German culture along lines suggested by Schopenhauer and Wagner. In 1873, Nietzsche also began to accumulate notes that would be posthumously published as Philosophy in the Tragic Age of the Greeks. During this time, in the circle of the Wagners, Nietzsche met Malwida von Meysenbug and Hans von Bülow, and also began a friendship with Paul Rée, who in 1876 influenced him in dismissing the pessimism in his early writings. However, he was deeply disappointed by the Bayreuth Festival of 1876, where the banality of the shows and the baseness of the public repelled him. He was also alienated by Wagner's championing of 'German culture', which Nietzsche thought a contradiction in terms, as well as by Wagner's celebration of his fame among the German public. All this contributed to Nietzsche's subsequent decision to distance himself from Wagner.

With the publication of Human, All Too Human in 1878 (a book of aphorisms on subjects ranging from metaphysics to morality and from religion to the sexes) Nietzsche's reaction against the pessimistic philosophy of Wagner and Schopenhauer became evident, as well as the influence of Afrikan Spir's Denken und Wirklichkeit.[15] Nietzsche's friendship with Deussen and Rohde cooled as well. In 1879, after a significant decline in health, Nietzsche had to resign his position at Basel. (Since his childhood, various disruptive illnesses had plagued him, including moments of shortsightedness that left him nearly blind, migraine headaches, and violent indigestion. The 1868 riding accident and diseases in 1870 may have aggravated these persistent conditions, which continued to affect him through his years at Basel, forcing him to take longer and longer holidays until regular work became impractical.)

Independent philosopher (1879–1888)

Because his illness drove him to find climates more conducive to his health, Nietzsche travelled frequently, and lived until 1889 as an independent author in different cities. He spent many summers in Sils Maria, near St. Moritz in Switzerland, and many winters in the Italian cities of Genoa, Rapallo and Turin and in the French city of Nice. In 1881, when France occupied Tunisia, he planned to travel to Tunis to view Europe from the outside, but later abandoned that idea (probably for health reasons).[16] While in Genoa, Nietzsche's failing eyesight prompted him to explore the use of typewriters as a means of continuing to write. He is known to have tried using the Hansen Writing Ball, a contemporary typewriter device.

Nietzsche occasionally returned to Naumburg to visit his family, and, especially during this time, he and his sister had repeated periods of conflict and reconciliation. He lived on his pension from Basel, but also received aid from friends. A past student of his, Peter Gast (born Heinrich Köselitz), became a sort of private secretary to Nietzsche. To the end of his life, Gast and Overbeck remained consistently faithful friends. Malwida von Meysenbug remained like a motherly patron even outside the Wagner circle. Soon Nietzsche made contact with the music-critic Carl Fuchs. Nietzsche stood at the beginning of his most productive period. Beginning with Human, All Too Human in 1878, Nietzsche would publish one book (or major section of a book) each year until 1888, his last year of writing, during which he completed five.



Lou Salomé, Paul Rée and Nietzsche, 1882

In 1882 Nietzsche published the first part of The Gay Science. That year he also met Lou Andreas Salomé, through Malwida von Meysenbug and Paul Rée. Nietzsche and Salomé spent the summer together in Tautenburg in Thuringia, often with Nietzsche's sister Elisabeth as a chaperone. Nietzsche, however, regarded Salomé less as an equal partner than as a gifted student. Salomé reports that he asked her to marry him and that she refused, though the reliability of her reports of events has come into question.[17] Nietzsche's relationship with Rée and Salomé broke up in the winter of 1882/1883, partially because of intrigues conducted by Nietzsche's sister Elisabeth. Amidst renewed bouts of illness, living in near isolation after a falling-out with his mother and sister regarding Salomé, Nietzsche fled to Rapallo. Here he wrote the first part of Thus Spoke Zarathustra in only ten days.

After severing his philosophical ties with Schopenhauer and his social ties with Wagner, Nietzsche had few remaining friends. Now, with the new style of Zarathustra, his work became even more alienating and the market received it only to the degree required by politeness. Nietzsche recognized this and maintained his solitude, though he often complained about it. His books remained largely unsold. In 1885 he printed only 40 copies of the fourth part of Zarathustra, and distributed only a fraction of these among close friends, including Helene von Druskowitz.

In 1883 he tried and failed to obtain a lecturing post at the University of Leipzig. It was made clear to him that, in view of the attitude towards Christianity and the concept of God expressed in Zarathustra, he had become in effect unemployable at any German University. The subsequent "feelings of revenge and resentment" embittered him. "And hence my rage since I have grasped in the broadest possible sense what wretched means (the depreciation of my good name, my character and my aims) suffice to take from me the trust of, and therewith the possibility of obtaining, pupils."[18]

In 1886 Nietzsche broke with his editor, Ernst Schmeitzner, disgusted by his anti-Semitic opinions. Nietzsche saw his own writings as "completely buried and unexhumeable in this anti-Semitic dump" of Schmeitzner—associating the editor with a movement that should be "utterly rejected with cold contempt by every sensible mind".[19] He then printed Beyond Good and Evil at his own expense, and issued in 1886–1887 second editions of his earlier works (The Birth of Tragedy, Human, All Too Human, Dawn, and The Gay Science), accompanied by new prefaces in which he reconsidered his earlier works. Thereafter, he saw his work as completed for a time and hoped that soon a readership would develop. In fact, interest in Nietzsche's thought did increase at this time, if rather slowly and in a way hardly perceived by him. During these years Nietzsche met Meta von Salis, Carl Spitteler, and also Gottfried Keller. In 1886 his sister Elisabeth married the anti-Semite Bernhard Förster and traveled to Paraguay to found Nueva Germania, a "Germanic" colony—a plan to which Nietzsche responded with mocking laughter.[20] Through correspondence, Nietzsche's relationship with Elisabeth continued on the path of conflict and reconciliation, but they would meet again only after his collapse. He continued to have frequent and painful attacks of illness, which made prolonged work impossible. In 1887 Nietzsche wrote the polemic On the Genealogy of Morals.

During the same year Nietzsche encountered the work of Fyodor Dostoevsky, with whom he felt an immediate kinship.[21] He also exchanged letters with Hippolyte Taine, and then also with Georg Brandes. Brandes, who had started to teach the philosophy of Søren Kierkegaard in the 1870s, wrote to Nietzsche asking him to read Kierkegaard, to which Nietzsche replied that he would come to Copenhagen and read Kierkegaard with him. However, before fulfilling this undertaking, he slipped too far into sickness. In the beginning of 1888, in Copenhagen, Brandes delivered one of the first lectures on Nietzsche's philosophy.

Although Nietzsche had in 1886 announced (at the end of On The Genealogy of Morality) a new work with the title The Will to Power: Attempt at a Revaluation of All Values, he eventually seems to have abandoned this particular approach and instead used some of the draft passages to compose Twilight of the Idols and The Antichrist (both written in 1888).[22]

His health seemed to improve, and he spent the summer in high spirits. In the fall of 1888 his writings and letters began to reveal a higher estimation of his own status and "fate." He overestimated the increasing response to his writings, especially to the recent polemic, The Case of Wagner. On his 44th birthday, after completing Twilight of the Idols and The Antichrist, he decided to write the autobiography Ecce Homo. In the preface to this work—which suggests Nietzsche was well aware of the interpretive difficulties his work would generate—he declares, "Hear me! For I am such and such a person. Above all, do not mistake me for someone else."[23] In December, Nietzsche began a correspondence with August Strindberg, and thought that, short of an international breakthrough, he would attempt to buy back his older writings from the publisher and have them translated into other European languages. Moreover, he planned the publication of the compilation Nietzsche Contra Wagner and of the poems that composed his collection Dionysian-Dithyrambs.

Mental breakdown and death (1889–1900)



Photo by Hans Olde from the photographic series, The Ill Nietzsche, summer 1899

On January 3, 1889, Nietzsche suffered a mental collapse. Two policemen approached him after he caused a public disturbance in the streets of Turin. What actually happened remains unknown, but an often-repeated tale states that Nietzsche witnessed the whipping of a horse at the other end of the Piazza Carlo Alberto, ran to the horse, threw his arms up around its neck to protect the horse, and then collapsed to the ground.[24]

In the following few days, Nietzsche sent short writings—known as the Wahnbriefe ("Madness Letters")—to a number of friends (including Cosima Wagner and Jacob Burckhardt). To his former colleague Burckhardt, Nietzsche wrote: "I have had Caiaphas put in fetters. Also, last year I was crucified by the German doctors in a very drawn-out manner. Wilhelm, Bismarck, and all anti-Semites abolished."[25] Additionally, he commanded the German emperor to go to Rome to be shot, and summoned the European powers to take military action against Germany.[26]

On January 6, 1889 Burckhardt showed the letter he had received from Nietzsche to Overbeck. The following day Overbeck received a similarly revealing letter, and decided that Nietzsche's friends had to bring him back to Basel. Overbeck traveled to Turin and brought Nietzsche to a psychiatric clinic in Basel. By that time Nietzsche appeared fully in the grip of a serious mental illness, and his mother Franziska decided to transfer him to a clinic in Jena under the direction of Otto Binswanger. From November 1889 to February 1890 the art historian Julius Langbehn attempted to cure Nietzsche, claiming that the methods of the medical doctors were ineffective in treating Nietzsche's condition. Langbehn assumed progressively greater control of Nietzsche until his secretiveness discredited him. In March 1890 Franziska removed Nietzsche from the clinic, and in May 1890 brought him to her home in Naumburg. During this process Overbeck and Gast contemplated what to do with Nietzsche's unpublished works. In January 1889 they proceeded with the planned release of Twilight of the Idols, by that time already printed and bound. In February they ordered a fifty copy private edition of Nietzsche contra Wagner, but the publisher C. G. Naumann secretly printed one hundred. Overbeck and Gast decided to withhold publishing The Antichrist and Ecce Homo because of their more radical content. Nietzsche's reception and recognition enjoyed their first surge.

Peter Gast would "correct" Nietzsche's writings even after the philosopher's breakdown and did so without his approval—an action severely criticized by contemporary Nietzsche scholars.

In 1893 Nietzsche's sister Elisabeth returned from Nueva Germania (in Paraguay) following the suicide of her husband. She read and studied Nietzsche's works, and piece by piece took control of them and of their publication. Overbeck eventually suffered dismissal, and Gast finally cooperated. After the death of Franziska in 1897 Nietzsche lived in Weimar, where Elisabeth cared for him and allowed people, including Rudolf Steiner (who in 1895 had written one of the first books praising Nietzsche)[27] to visit her uncommunicative brother. Elisabeth at one point went so far as to employ Steiner–at a time when he was still an ardent fighter against any mysticism–as a tutor to help her to understand her brother's philosophy. Steiner abandoned the attempt after only a few months, declaring that it was impossible to teach her anything about philosophy.[28]

Nietzsche's mental illness was originally diagnosed as tertiary syphilis, in accordance with a prevailing medical paradigm of the time. Although most commentators regard his breakdown as unrelated to his philosophy Georges Bataille drops dark hints (""man incarnate" must also go mad")[29] and René Girard's postmortem psychoanalysis posits a worshipful rivalry with Richard Wagner.[30] The diagnosis of syphilis was challenged, and manic-depressive illness with periodic psychosis, followed by vascular dementia was put forward by Cybulska[31] prior Schain's;[32] and Sax's studies;.[33] Orth and Trimble postulate frontotemporal dementia,[34] while other researchers[35] propose a syndrome called CADASIL.

In 1898 and 1899 Nietzsche suffered at least two strokes, which partially paralysed him and left him unable to speak or walk. After contracting pneumonia in mid-August 1900 he had another stroke during the night of August 24 / August 25, and died about noon on August 25.[36] Elisabeth had him buried beside his father at the church in Röcken bei Lützen. His friend, Gast, gave his funeral oration, proclaiming: "Holy be your name to all future generations!"[37] Nietzsche had written in Ecce Homo (at the time of the funeral still unpublished) of his fear that one day his name would be regarded as "holy".

Elisabeth Förster-Nietzsche compiled The Will to Power from Nietzsche's unpublished notebooks, and published it posthumously. Because his sister arranged the book based on her own conflation of several of Nietzsche's early outlines, and took great liberties with the material, the consensus holds that it does not reflect Nietzsche's intent. Indeed, Mazzino Montinari, the editor of Nietzsche's Nachlass, called it a forgery in The 'Will to Power' does not exist. For example, Elisabeth removed aphorism 35 of The Antichrist, where Nietzsche rewrote a passage of the Bible (see The Will to Power and Nietzsche's criticisms of anti-Semitism and nationalism).

Citizenship, nationality, ethnicity

Nietzsche is commonly classified as a German philosopher.[38] The modern unified nation-state called Germany did not yet exist at the time of his birth, but the German Confederation of states did, and Nietzsche was a citizen of one of these, Prussia—for a time. When he accepted his post at Basel, Nietzsche applied for the annulment of his Prussian citizenship.[39] The official response confirming the revocation of his citizenship came in a document dated April 17, 1869,[40] and for the rest of his life he remained officially stateless.

According to a common myth, Nietzsche's ancestors were Polish. Nietzsche himself subscribed to this story toward the end of his life. He wrote in 1888, "My ancestors were Polish noblemen (Nietzky); the type seems to have been well preserved despite three generations of German mothers."[41] At one point Nietzsche becomes even more adamant about his Polish Identity. “I am a pure-blooded Polish nobleman, without a single drop of bad blood, certainly not German blood.”[42] On yet another occasion Nietzsche stated “Germany is a great nation only because its people have so much Polish blood in their veins [...] I am proud of my Polish descent.”[43] Nietzsche believed his name might have been Germanized, in one letter claiming, "I was taught to ascribe the origin of my blood and name to Polish noblemen who were called Niëtzky and left their home and nobleness about a hundred years ago, finally yielding to unbearable suppression: they were Protestants."[44]

Most scholars dispute Nietzsche's account of his family's origins. Hans von Müller debunked the genealogy put forward by Nietzsche's sister in favor of a Polish noble heritage.[45] Max Oehler, the curator of Nietzsche Archive at Weimar, argued that all of Nietzsche's ancestors bore German names, even the wives' families.[41] Oehler claims that Nietzsche came from a long line of German Lutheran clergymen on both sides of his family, and modern scholars regard the claim of Nietzsche's Polish ancestry as "pure invention."[46] Colli and Montinari, the editors of Nietzsche's assembled letters, gloss Nietzsche's claims as a "mistaken belief" and "without foundation."[47] The name Nietzsche itself is not a Polish name, but an exceptionally common one throughout central Germany, in this and cognate forms (such as Nitsche and Nitzke). The name derives from the forename Nikolaus, abbreviated to Nick; assimilated with the Slavic Nitz, it first became Nitsche and then Nietzsche.[41]

It is not known why Nietzsche wanted to be thought of as Polish. According to biographer R. J. Hollingdale, Nietzsche's propagation of the Polish ancestry myth may have been part of the latter's "campaign against Germany".[41]

Philosophy



Friedrich Nietzsche, 1882

Nietzsche’s works remain controversial, and there is widespread disagreement about their interpretation and significance. Part of the difficulty in interpreting Nietzsche arises from the uniquely provocative style of his philosophical writing. Nietzsche frequently delivered trenchant critiques of Christianity in the most offensive and blasphemous terms possible given the context of 19th century Europe. These aspects of Nietzsche's style run counter to traditional values in philosophical writing, and they alienated him from the academic establishment both in his time and, to a lesser extent, today. Some analytic philosophers dismiss Nietzsche as inconsistent and speculative, producing something other than "real" philosophy.

A few of the themes that Nietzsche scholars have devoted the most attention to include Nietzsche's views on morality, his view that "God is dead" (and along with it any sort of God's-eye view on the world thus leading to perspectivism), his notions of the will to power and Übermensch, and his suggestion of eternal return.

Morality

In Daybreak Nietzsche begins his "Campaign against Morality".[48] He calls himself an "immoralist" and harshly criticizes the prominent moral schemes of his day: Christianity, Kantianism, and utilitarianism. In Ecce Homo Nietzsche called the establishment of moral systems based on a dichotomy of good and evil a "calamitous error",[49] and wished to initiate a re-evaluation of the values of the Judeo-Christian world.[50] He indicates his desire to bring about a new, more naturalistic source of value in the vital impulses of life itself.

In both these works, Nietzsche's genealogical account of the development of master-slave morality occupies a central place. Nietzsche presents master-morality as the original system of morality—perhaps best associated with Homeric Greece. Here, value arises as a contrast between good and bad, or between 'life-affirming' and 'life-denying': wealth, strength, health, and power, the sort of traits found in a Homeric hero, count as good; while bad is associated with the poor, weak, sick, and pathetic, the sort of traits conventionally associated with slaves in ancient times.

Slave-morality, in contrast, comes about as a reaction to master-morality. Nietzsche associates slave-morality with the Jewish and Christian traditions. Here, value emerges from the contrast between good and evil: good being associated with other-worldliness, charity, piety, restraint, meekness, and submission; evil seen as worldly, cruel, selfish, wealthy, and aggressive. Nietzsche sees slave-morality born out of the ressentiment of slaves. It works to overcome the slave's own sense of inferiority before the (better-off) masters. It does so by making out slave weakness to be a matter of choice, by, e.g., relabeling it as "meekness."

Nietzsche sees the slave-morality as a source of the nihilism that has overtaken Europe. In Nietzsche's eyes, modern Europe, and its Christianity, exists in a hypocritical state due to a tension between master and slave morality, both values contradictorily determining, to varying degrees, the values of most Europeans (who are "motley"). Nietzsche calls for exceptional people to no longer be ashamed of their uniqueness in the face of a supposed morality-for-all, which Nietzsche deems to be harmful to the flourishing of exceptional people. However, Nietzsche cautions that morality, per se, is not bad; it is good for the masses, and should be left to them. Exceptional people, on the other hand, should follow their own "inner law." A favorite motto of Nietzsche, taken from Pindar, reads: "Become what you are."

Death of God, nihilism, perspectivism

The statement "God is dead", occurring in several of Nietzsche's works (notably in The Gay Science), has become one of his best-known remarks. On the basis of it, most commentators[51] regard Nietzsche as an atheist; others (such as Kaufmann) suggest that this statement reflects a more subtle understanding of divinity. In Nietzsche's view, recent developments in modern science and the increasing secularization of European society had effectively 'killed' the Christian God, who had served as the basis for meaning and value in the West for more than a thousand years.

Nietzsche claimed the death of God would eventually lead to the loss of any universal perspective on things, and along with it any coherent sense of objective truth.[52] Instead we would retain only our own multiple, diverse, and fluid perspectives. This view has acquired the name "perspectivism".

Alternatively, the death of God may lead beyond bare perspectivism to outright nihilism, the belief that nothing has any inherent importance and that life lacks purpose. As Heidegger put the problem, "If God as the suprasensory ground and goal of all reality is dead, if the suprasensory world of the Ideas has suffered the loss of its obligatory and above it its vitalizing and upbuilding power, then nothing more remains to which man can cling and by which he can orient himself."[53] Developing this idea, Nietzsche wrote Thus Spoke Zarathustra, therein introducing the concept of a value-creating Übermensch. According to Lampert, "the death of God must be followed by a long twilight of piety and nihilism (II. 19; III. 8). […] Zarathustra's gift of the superman is given to a mankind not aware of the problem to which the superman is the solution."[54]

Will to power

A basic element in Nietzsche's philosophical outlook is the "will to power" (der Wille zur Macht), which provides a basis for understanding human behavior. In a wide sense of a term, the will to power is more important element than pressure for adaptation or survival.[55] According to Nietzsche, only in limited situations the drive for conservation is precedent over the will to power. The natural condition of life, according to him, is one of profusion.[56] In its later forms Nietzsche's concept of the will to power applies to all living things, suggesting that adaptation and the struggle to survive is a secondary drive in the evolution of animals, less important than the desire to expand one’s power. Nietzsche eventually took this concept further still, and speculated that it may apply to inorganic nature as well. He transformed the idea of matter as centers of force into matter as centers of will to power. Nietzsche wanted to dispense with the atomistic theory of matter, a theory which he viewed as a relic of the metaphysics of substance.[57] One study of Nietzsche defines his fully developed concept of the will to power as "the element from which derive both the quantitative difference of related forces and the quality that devolves into each force in this relation" revealing the will to power as "the principle of the synthesis of forces."[58]

Nietzsche's notion of the will to power can also be viewed as a response to Schopenhauer's "will to live." Writing a generation before Nietzsche, Schopenhauer had regarded the entire universe and everything in it as driven by a primordial will to live, thus resulting in all creatures' desire to avoid death and to procreate. Nietzsche, however, challenges Schopenhauer's account and suggests that people and animals really want power; living in itself appears only as a subsidiary aim—something necessary to promote one's power. Defending his view, Nietzsche describes instances where people and animals willingly risk their lives to gain power—most notably in instances like competitive fighting and warfare. Once again, Nietzsche seems to take part of his inspiration from the ancient Homeric Greek texts he knew well: Greek heroes and aristocrats or "masters" did not desire mere living (they often died quite young and risked their lives in battle) but wanted power, glory, and greatness. In this regard he often mentions the common Greek theme of agon or contest.

In addition to Schopenhauer's psychological views, Nietzsche contrasts his notion of the will to power with many of the other most popular psychological views of his day, such as that of utilitarianism. Utilitarianism—a philosophy mainly promoted, in Nietzsche's days and before, by British thinkers such as Bentham and Stuart Mill—claims that all people fundamentally want to be happy. But this conception of happiness found in utilitarianism Nietzsche rejected as something limited to, and characteristic of, English society only.[59] Also Platonism and Christian neo-Platonism–which claim that people ultimately want to achieve unity with The Good or with God–are philosophies he criticizes. In each case, Nietzsche argues that the "will to power" provides a more useful and general explanation of human behavior.

Übermensch

Another concept important to an understanding of Nietzsche's thought is the Übermensch. While interpretations of Nietzsche's overman vary wildly, here are a few of his quotes from Thus Spoke Zarathustra (Prologue, §§3–4):

"I teach you the overman. Man is something that shall be overcome. What have you done to overcome him? … All beings so far have created something beyond themselves; and do you want to be the ebb of this great flood, and even go back to the beasts rather than overcome man? What is ape to man? A laughing stock or painful embarrassment. And man shall be that to overman: a laughingstock or painful embarrassment. You have made your way from worm to man, and much in you is still worm. Once you were apes, and even now, too, man is more ape than any ape.... The overman is the meaning of the earth. Let your will say: the overman shall be the meaning of the earth.... Man is a rope, tied between beast and overman—a rope over an abyss … what is great in man is that he is a bridge and not an en Eternal return

The idea of eternal return occurs in a parable in Section 341 of The Gay Science, and also in the chapter "Of the Vision and the Riddle" in Thus Spoke Zarathustra, among other places.[60] Nietzsche calls the idea "horrifying and paralyzing", and says that its burden is the "heaviest weight" imaginable.("das schwerste Gewicht")[61] The wish for the eternal return of all events would mark the ultimate affirmation of life, a reaction to Schopenhauer's praise of denying the will–to–live. To comprehend eternal recurrence in his thought, and to not merely come to peace with it but to embrace it, requires amor fati, "love of fate":[62]

Reading and influence

The residence of Nietzsche's last three years, along with archive in Weimar, Germany, which holds many of Nietzsche's papers

As a philologist, Nietzsche had a thorough knowledge of Greek philosophy. He read Immanuel Kant, John Stuart Mill, Arthur Schopenhauer and Afrikan Spir,[63] who became his main opponents in his philosophy, and later Spinoza, whom he saw as his "precursor" in some respects[64] but as a personification of the "ascetic ideal" in others. However, Nietzsche referred to Kant as a "moral fanatic", Mill as a "blockhead", and of Spinoza he said: "How much of personal timidity and vulnerability does this masquerade of a sickly recluse betray?"[65]

Nietzsche's philosophy, while highly innovative and revolutionary, was indebted to many predecessors, including the pre-Socratic Greek thinker Heraclitus. Heraclitus was known for the rejection of the concept of being as a constant and eternal principle of universe, and his embrace of "flux" and incessant change. His symbolism of the world as "child play" marked by amoral spontaneity and lack of definite rules was appreciated by Nietzsche.[66] From his Heraclitean sympathy Nietzsche was also a vociferous detractor of Parmenides, who opposed Heraclitus and believed all world is a single Being with no change at all.[67]

Nietzsche expressed admiration for 17th century French moralists such as La Rochefoucauld, Jean de La Bruyère and Vauvenargues,[68] as well as for Stendhal.[69] The organicism of Paul Bourget influenced Nietzsche,[70] as did that of Rudolf Virchow and Alfred Espinas.[71] Nietzsche early learned of Darwinism through Friedrich Lange.[72] Notably, he also read some of the posthumous works of Charles Baudelaire,[73] Tolstoy's My Religion, Ernest Renan's Life of Jesus and Fyodor Dostoyevsky's The Possessed.[73][74] Nietzsche called Dostoevsky "the only psychologist from whom I have anything to learn."[75] Comments in several passages suggest that he responded strongly and favorably to the work of Ralph Waldo Emerson. While Nietzsche never mentions Max Stirner, the similarities in their ideas have prompted a minority of interpreters to suggest he both read and was influenced by him.[76] In 1861 Friedrich Nietzsche wrote an enthusiastic essay on his "favorite poet", Friedrich Hölderlin, mostly forgotten at that time[77].

Reception

Nietzsche’s works did not reach a wide readership during his active writing career. However, in 1888 Georg Brandes (an influential Danish critic) aroused considerable excitement about Nietzsche through a series of lectures he gave at the University of Copenhagen. Then in 1894 Lou Andreas-Salomé published her book, Friedrich Nietzsche in seinen Werken (Friedrich Nietzsche in His Works). Andreas-Salomé had known Nietzsche well in the early 1880s, and she returned to the subject of Nietzsche, years later, in her work Lebensrückblick – Grundriß einiger Lebenserinnerungen (Looking Back: Memoirs) (written in 1932), which covered her intellectual relationships with Nietzsche, Rilke, and Freud. Nietzsche himself had acquired the publication-rights for his earlier works in 1886 and began a process of editing and re-formulation that placed the body of his work in a more coherent perspective.

In the years after his death in 1900, Nietzsche's works became better known, and readers have responded to them in complex and sometimes controversial ways. Many Germans eventually discovered his appeals for greater individualism and personality development in Thus Spoke Zarathustra, but responded to those appeals divergently. He had some following among left-wing Germans in the 1890s; in 1894–1895 German conservatives wanted to ban his work as subversive. During the late 19th century Nietzsche's ideas were commonly associated with anarchist movements and appear to have had influence within them, particularly in France and the United States.[78] The poet W.B. Yeats helped to raise awareness of Nietzsche in Ireland.[79] H.L. Mencken produced translations of Nietzsche's works that helped to increase knowledge of his philosophy in the United States.

By World War I, Nietzsche had acquired a reputation as an inspiration for right-wing German militarism. German soldiers received copies of Thus Spoke Zarathustra as gifts during World War I.[80][81] The Dreyfus Affair provides another example of his reception: the French anti-semitic Right labelled the Jewish and Leftist intellectuals who defended Alfred Dreyfus as "Nietzscheans".[82] Nietzsche had a distinct appeal for many Zionist thinkers at the turn of the century. It has been argued that his work influenced Theodore Herzl,[83] and Martin Buber went so far as to extoll Nietzsche as a "creator" and "emissary of life".[84] Bertrand Russell, in his History of Western Philosophy was scathing about Nietzsche, calling his work the "mere power-phantasies of an invalid", referring to him as a "megalomaniac", and writing that he was a philosophical progenitor of the Nazis and fascists.[85]

Nietzsche's growing prominence suffered a severe setback when his works became closely associated with Adolf Hitler and the German Reich. Many political leaders of the twentieth century were at least superficially familiar with Nietzsche's ideas, although it is not always possible to determine whether or not they actually read his work. Hitler, for example, probably never read Nietzsche, and if he did, his reading was not extensive,[86] although he was a frequent visitor to the Nietzsche museum in Weimar and did use expressions of Nietzsche's, such as "lords of the earth" in Mein Kampf.[87] The Nazis made selective use of Nietzsche's philosophy. Mussolini and Charles de Gaulle read Nietzsche.[88][89] It has been suggested that Theodore Roosevelt read Nietzsche and was profoundly influenced by him,[90] and in more recent years, Richard Nixon read Nietzsche with "curious interest".[91]

A decade after World War II, there was a revival of Nietzsche's philosophical writings thanks to exhaustive translations and analyses by Walter Kaufmann and R.J. Hollingdale. Others, well known philosophers in their own right, wrote commentaries on Nietzsche’s philosophy, including Martin Heidegger, who produced a four-volume study. Many 20th century thinkers (particularly in the tradition of continental philosophy) cite him as a profound influence, including Martin Heidegger, Jean-Paul Sartre, Leo Strauss, Albert Camus, Michel Foucault, Jacques Derrida, and Gilles Deleuze, whose philosophy of immanence has significant similarities to Nietzsche's will to power. In the Anglo-American tradition he has had a profound influence on Bernard Williams due to the scholarship of Walter Kaufmann and R. J. Hollingdale, which rehabilitated Nietzsche as a philosopher, and American philosophers such as Allan Bloom, Alexander Nehamas, William E. Connolly and Brian Leiter continue to study him today. A vocal minority of recent Nietzschean interpreters (Bruce Detwiler, Fredrick Appel, Domenico Losurdo, Abir Taha) have contested what they consider the popular but erroneous egalitarian misrepresentation of Nietzsche's "aristocratic radicalism".

Works











No comments: